Monday, November 18, 2013

Relativism and Morality - Response to Lenn Goodman's "Some Moral Minima"

Not my most proud piece but still a reflection of my work. This was a response to the "Some Moral Minima" by Lenn Goodman.  You might be able to read it here: http://muse.jhu.edu/login?auth=0&type=summary&url=/journals/good_society/v019/19.1.goodman.html



Relativism and Morality

            Relativism allows for an understanding of practices, customs, and values amongst different societies.  When considering the morals of others, relativism can often be necessary to comes to terms with different views of what is considered appropriate and unacceptable.  However, in some instances relativism does not, and cannot, provide an acceptable substitution for what should be considered a set of unanimously respected principles. Lenn Goodman, a philosophy professor at Vanderbilt University, having addressed the issue of morality regarding genocide, famine and germ warfare, terrorism, hostages and child warriors, slavery, polygamy, incest, rape, and clitoridectomy, challenges relativism and asserts her position that such issues are unequivocally wrong. Though my perspective on some of the issues Len Goodman argues allows for relativism, I am ultimately in agreement that there are some practices that are universally wrong; these such actions and customs, despite cultural and geographical differences, are and will always be a crime against humanity.

Humanity can be defined as the state of being a human, or humans collectively. While at the same time, the word humanity can refer to ones “humaneness” or inherit benevolence. Such definitions are powerful; it gives rise to the understanding that the condition of being human is more than just biological.  Despite diversities in culture, religion, and customs, there is a uniform characteristic that links humans. That is, the ability to feel and interpret emotions, thus illuminating ones sense of self and connectedness to their fellow man.  Such a knowledge of ones’ own emotions and that of others lends an understanding of the value, and thereby, right, to life.

            Such right to life, and more complexly, the right to respect of one’s humanity, is a primary philosophy that Goodman’s position urges. Such rights include individuality, which she argues is what genocide, famine, and germ warfare seeks to destroy.  While murder destroys a human subject, genocide targets a way of life; genocide is worse than murder because of its intent. The political use of famine and germ warfare targets humanity in the same way. Its purpose being power. Goodman’s stance on such cases are agreeable, for genocide is wrong not just for the fact that is seeks to murder individuals or masses, but for the hatred and disregard for the rights of humanity and the denial of one’s individual and cultural differences therein. With the use of famine and germ warfare those inflicted are eradicated, and from my understanding, are a form of genocide in themselves.

            Violence as a means for power is not limited to genocide, but is also apparent in terrorism, hostages, and the making of child warriors. Goodman claims that terrorism comes from nihilism, the lack of morals and values, and in the act of fighting for the morals and values it seeks, it produces nihilism again by negating the rationale it attempts to conjure (Goodman, 2010). This rings truth, for can we not witness that the act of violence and intimidation is contradictory to the outcome it wishes to serve? For instance, terrorist who engage in a suicide mission seek moral amnesty for the sacrifice of their own life, yet the action itself eclipses the virtue such terrorist finds in their sacrifice.  Goodman (2010) expresses this well, stating “Terrorist explode the values they claim to fight for.  Their victims’ blood blurs and blots whatever ends were meant to justify the carnage” (p. 89). The act of hostage taking is quite similar; persons are used for the leverage they offer, therefore becoming an object of terrorism. Similarly, the use of child warriors takes advantage of the easily manipulated essence of children, objectifying them and then leaving them with psychological scarring they must endure for their lifetime. Such acts are horrific in any society, their outcomes are tragic. I feel they are a brutal disregard for human life and all that it implies. 

            Perhaps even more torturous than death is slavery.  Goodman’s stance on slavery is that it is the ultimate exploitation of a person.  Using another as a tool for one’s self does not account for the victims’ interest, needs, or wants, rather making them subordinate to the needs and wants of others (Goodman, 2010). Indeed, slavery abuses and restricts one from their sense of self and is wrong on many levels. Victims of slavery are required to dismiss their ownership of self and to perform as a means to someone else’s end. This is a fundamental denial of human rights. Extended from this thought is my position on rape, which is much like that of Goodman’s, in that such an act is the most degrading and unconditionally acceptable form of a manipulation unto another. Goodman (2010) states “rape is exploitative, objectifying, and yes, again violative. But what it violates is not just another’s body but that other’s personhood, invested, deeply in one’s sexuality” (p. 92). The act is demoralizing and humiliating. It violates the victims’ body, self-confidence, self-image and ultimately ones’ psyche.  “Rape perverts and blasphemes against the trust and intimacy that give sexuality its natural and transcendent meanings” (p. 92).  Blasphemy is a perfect word in this case as such an assault attacks a victim so deeply that there is no greater form of disregard for another’s sexuality and intimate sanctity. In this notion, the custom of clitoridectomy is just as appalling in that it denies a woman of her physiological right to the pleasures of intimacy (Goodman, 2010).  The lack of sexual pleasures makes it difficult for a woman to form an intimate bond with her partner - bonds which are inherit in humanity.

            While in these mentioned instances I can agree with Goodman’s position on universal wrongness, I find relativism possible in the remaining concerns she speaks of: polygamy and incest. According to Goodman, “Polygamy transforms the nature of marriage. That is evident in the apologetics and conditionals that so often speak of the need or fairness by a husband to his wives.  The telling subtext is that it is the husband who makes moral choices here, the wives who are the recipients of treatment, fair or unfair, invidious or even handed” (p. 91). In this case and from the scope of my own culture, I can concur that polygamy is morally unjust, yet considering this is a choice in most instances and often derives from religious beliefs I regard it with a relativist perspective.  Kurt Mosser (2010) describes that arguments as seen through the lens of relativism can be understood in the context of one’s society; what is virtuous as it relates to one’s culture may differ as it relates to another.  I feel that incest, too, can be judged morally right or wrong through relativism assuming that there is not a condition of rape involved, and family members are not directly related. However, Goodman does not place cultural limits on such an issue.  She argues that incest violates the developing individual, affecting their hopes, aspirations, and their sense of self apart from their family unit (Goodman, 2010).

            Relativism in whole is challenged in the cases Goodman takes position on.  She describes no cultural, geographical, or even philosophical boundary that gives way for allowance of such practices.  Rather, Goodman speaks of a unanimous moral disregard that these practices empower and that humanity must take an undivided stand against.  These issues seek to find a common agreement of what humanity considers morally unacceptable.  Besides the few slight differences, I can endorse the claim that Lenn Goodman makes in asserting that there are certain practices that demoralize and violate the condition of humanity. Humanity itself begs for appreciation of life and tolerance on individuality.  Humanness seeks to express itself and to create physical and emotional bonds with its kin; it creates friendships, alliances, and communities that lends support and praises the diversities of its people.  Humanity as previously noted can be used to define the benevolence, or kindness, of a person; therefore, in its own nature it mandates a basic, unanimous, and unchallenged set of moral requirements that pledge to uphold and respect its fragility and beauty.

Reference

 

Goodman, L. E. (2010). Some moral minima. The Good Society, 19(1), 87-94.

Mosser, K. (2010). Ethics & Social Responsibility. San Diego, CA: Bridgepoint Education, Inc.

No comments:

Post a Comment